Рostmodernism
Рostmodernism
Under the post-modern
onslaught, all boundaries and distinctions rapidly fall. Some of the losses
associated with the collapse of traditional distinctions have been trivial, but
others have been earthshaking, and there seems to be no way to distinguish
between the two in a post-modern context. People no longer know where the lines
fall.
Some sociologists believe we
are now moving into a new and very different type of society. The social
change, that began to accelerate 300 years ago, has continued at such a pace
that the theories and assumptions we had about modern society no longer explain
the society we find around us.
The
main characteristic of postmodernism
seems to be a loss of faith in the ideas of the Enlightenment. It is argued by
postmodernists that people have become disillusioned with the idea that we can
use science and rational thought to make the world a better place. People have
become disillusioned with the idea of progress. There is greater understanding
of negative effects of so-called ‘progress’, such as pollution, environmental damage
and damage to human populations.
We
are also seeing the disappearance
of old certainties.
In the past gender roles, ethnic differences, social class differences were all
clear cut and people generally conformed to societal expectations. Today the old
distinctions are blurring and people choose who they want to be, and how they
want to behave.
Postmodernists also argue
that other characteristics of modern
societies are disappearing.
- The big production companies making
vast quantities of the same product are becoming more diversified and
there has been a growth of small companies producing goods for very
specialized markets.
- New social movements are connecting
people across traditional class and ethnic boundaries; movements such as
gay rights, environmentalism, feminism, and new religious movements.
- The significance of nation states is in decline.
Today many multi-national companies are larger and have more power than
most countries, and within countries more provision is being privatized
and less is provided by the state.
- Employees are less likely to
have long-term careers and jobs for life, employment is more uncertain and there has been a
big increase in part-time, temporary and agency employment.
Despite
all this evidence, the concept of a postmodern society is a very controversial
one. Many sociologists accept that society is changing a great deal but do not
accept the term postmodern. Some sociologists, including Anthony Giddens, prefer to describe
society as in a stage of ‘late-modernity’.
Modernism
always celebrated the new and considered ideas from the past to be
‘old-fashioned’. Postmodernism borrows from the past and combines a wide range
of styles together - a ‘pick and mix’ approach. A good example of a postmodern
building is a shopping centre called the Trafford Centre, in Manchester. This
looks like St Paul's Cathedral from the front, a Norman castle from the back,
inside one section is the deck of an ocean liner, and in another is a Victorian
palm house.
Distinctions
between the cultures of the different social classes have been blurred, for
example by the use of opera as a theme tune for the football world cup. The
process of globalisation has also meant the blurring of traditional cultural
boundaries. Today Coca-Cola can be found in the remotest regions of the world.
Contemporary,
or postmodern, society is characterized by a newfound ability to control the
world of nature and worlds of illusion. It immerses people in a virtual
environment of images and simulations, and encourages the acting out of
desires, including desires that once seemed off-limits to action and
experience. Ultimately, it seeks to turn reality into a simulation and make
simulations seem real, so humanity will have the ability to control and create
its surroundings at will.
How
does postmodern society use this newfound power? It certainly has used it to
enormous good. But it has also used it to create an emerging worldwide culture
in which images, simulations, story lines, performances and rhetoric are
employed to manipulate the public and sell it products, phony candidates and
false ideas. Thus postmodern society turns out to be a realm of illusion
in more than one sense.
Stephen
Connor says that the "concept of postmodernism cannot be said to have
crystallized until about the mid-1970's…”. Modernity had received some strong
criticism, and it was becoming more and more tenable to assert that the
postmodern had come to stay, but it took some time before scholarship really
jumped on the bandwagon. At this point it is important to distinguish between postmodern
and postmodernism. Postmodern refers to a period of time, whereas
postmodernism refers to a distinct ideology. As Veith points out,
"If the modern era is over, we are all postmodern, even though we
reject the tenets of postmodernism.
So
exactly what is postmodernism? The situation is profoundly complex and
ambiguous. But basically speaking, postmodernism is anti-foundationalism,
or anti-worldview. It denies the existence of any universal truth or
standards. Jean-Francois Lyotard, perhaps the most influential writer in
postmodern thought, defines postmodernism as "incredulity towards
metannarratives." For all intents and purposes, a metanarrative is
a worldview: a network of elementary assumptions. . . in terms of which every
aspect of our experience and knowledge is interrelated and interpreted.
Metanarratives are, according to postmodernist scholar Patricia Waugh,
"Large-scale theoretical interpretations purportedly of universal
application." The postmodernist's, it would seem, would tolerate having a
coherent worldview so long as it is kept from being asserted as universal in
its application. This is not the case though. The goal, so to speak, of
postmodernism is to not only reject metanarratives, but also the belief in
coherence. Not only is any worldview which sees itself as foundational for all
others oppressive, belief that one may even have a coherent worldview is
rejected as well. Nevertheless, there are many worldviews around today, and the
postmodernist finds it to be his responsibility to critique, or
"deconstruct" as they call it, such worldviews and "flatten them
out," so to speak, so that no one particular approach or belief is more
"true" than any other. What constitutes truth, then, is relative to
the individual or community holding the belief.
As
we have seen, for the postmodern thinker, there are no absolute truths or
foundations to work from. Properly speaking, then, postmodernism is not a
worldview per se; it does not attempt to construct a model or
paradigm that orders reality; reality alludes attempts at conformity for the
postmodernist, and so he deconstructs all attempts at creating such
absolute foundations. Modernity and Christianity debated as to which view was
true; postmodernism attacks both Christianity and modernity because they claim
to be "true." Christianity affirms certain necessary beliefs that
must be assumed in order to make sense out of the world (e.g., that the triune
God exists, that he is both transcendent and immanent, that the Bible is his
Word). Postmodernism rejects the idea that reality makes sense in any absolute
fashion, and reduces any construction to personal or cultural bias. Truth is a
social construct, pragmatically justified, so as to make it one of many culturally
conditioned approaches to the world. Postmodernism, then, is not so much an orthodoxy
(a positive belief system or worldview), as it is an orthopraxy (a
series of methods for analysis).
In continuing
to remove the possibility of any ultimate knowledge, postmodernism confuses the
traditional distinction between the subject of knowledge (the knower) and the
object of knowledge (the thing being known). Man does not sit back and
passively receive knowledge about the world; rather, man's interpretation is,
ultimately, the way the world actually is, as it is revealed to him, or
to a culture. This confusion of subject and object has earned postmodernism the
labels of nihilism and relativism. Logic, science, history, and morality are
not universal and absolute; they are the constructs of our own experience and
interpretations of that experience.
Why
do the postmodernists draw these conclusions? As we saw above the idea that
reality was orderly and that man was simply a passive observer was called into
question. Kant's "Copernican Revolution" in philosophy argued that
the mind "brings something to the objects it experiences . . . The mind
imposes its way of knowing upon its objects.” It is the object that conforms to
the mind, not the mind to the object. It would seem then that reality is what
we perceive it to be. Charles Mackenzie observes:
If
in knowing an object the human mind virtually creates knowledge, the question
has been raised then, What is the external world when it is not being
perceived? Kant replied that we cannot know a thing-in-itself (ding an sich).
The world, as it exists apart from our experience, is unknowable.
As
such reality, as it really is, is unknowable. The "thing in itself,"
cannot be known. The only thing that can be known is our personal experience
and our interpretation of that experience. Since each person's experience is
all that can be known, it cannot be concluded that man can know anything in any
absolute sense. All one has is his own finite, limited experience. Logic,
science, history, and ethics are human disciplines that must, and do, reflect
human insufficiency and subjectivity.
Another
reason the postmodernists draw these conclusions comes from the fact that the
existentialists, with their rejection of rationalism and empiricism, focused
philosophy on the human experience, especially as it is communicated through
language. Language is the way man expresses these experiences of the world,
therefore to understand the world, as best we can, we must look to what is said
about reality. But subjectivism is all we can have since the best we can do is
experience and interpret what others have experienced and interpreted reality
to be, and so the spiral continues downward. Thus, for the postmodernists, any
assertion of absolute knowledge is seriously questioned and ultimately
rejected. Therefore history is seen as a series of metaphors rather than an
account of events as they actually happened. After all, the one
recording the events was writing and recording the events as he saw them.
Someone else may have seen it differently had they been there. In issues of
morality no one particular view is seen as foundational. Rather, each
culture's, and ultimately each individual's, view on ethics is just as valid as
the next. This view is the basis for the assumptions of
"Multiculturalism," and the "Political Correctness"
movement in today's society. Rather than affirming any one morality as
absolute, every person's moral persuasion is to be respected no matter what it
is, and language must be revised so as to not favor any one outlook and thus
offend another.
Irving
Kristol, a fellow at the American Enterprize Institute, describes the current
time as "a shaking of the foundations of the modern world."
Allen
says: A massive intellectual revolution is taking place that is perhaps as
great as that which marked off the modern world from the Middle Ages . . . The
principles forged during the Enlightenment … which formed the foundations of
the modernmentality, are crumbling.
The
collapse of Enlightenment Humanism is imminent, and the attacks on it are from
all angles. From religious conservatives to scientific liberals, the desire to
overhaul the presuppositions of modernity is a shared goal, although the
motives differ greatly. Christians welcome the opportunity for credible public
discourse concerning their faith, and many scientists are eager to see a shift
in scientific outlook that will account for the anomalies that modern science
has avoided. These are exciting times, times when the church should be alert.
In
a postmodern world Christianity is intellectually relevant. With the demise of
the absoluteness of human reason and science, the super-natural, that which is
not empirical, is once again open to consideration. The marketplace of ideas is
wide open, and opportunities abound. It is important that the church understand
these important times in which it finds itself. But in addition to opening the
door once again to the Christian faith, postmodernism, with its critical apparatus,
has a few lessons for the church to learn.
What
is interesting is that postmodernism strikes at the very same thing God did:
language. Without language, logic and science are meaningless; they have no
application. As we have seen, its each man for himself in his own private
world. The arrogant, pseudo-unity that man had claimed to find was now just one
of the many ways of looking at things. Logic and science were now relative to
cultural interpretation. Like the people at the Tower of Babel, modern man has
been fragmented and scattered. There is no center of discourse any longer.
In
this light perhaps the most significant contribution of postmodernism is that
it reminds us of our finitude. It reminds us that God is creator and we are his
creation. It tells us that he must be the beginning of all of our thinking,
that apart from him we could know nothing.
For
our personal life, postmodernism shows us the futility of autonomy. It forces
those of us who know Christ back to the basics of depending on Christ for
everything, whether it is salvation or standards. That in him we have meaning
and purpose for our lives; he is the vine, we are the branches, and apart from
him we can do nothing.
To
sum it up, postmodernism need not be seen as a mortal enemy. In many ways it
drives us back to complete and total dependence on God. It reminds us that he
is the foundation for every area of life, whether it is logic or law. It shows
us that there exist no neutral, impartial domains that we can lean on in
addition to him. Postmodernism points out that we all have presuppositions, and
that no one is unbiased. We all bring our assumptions to our experience; each
fact about the world is theory-laden. The question then becomes, "Which
presuppositions are true?" The answer is clear: the Christian worldview is
true. It alone is the only escape from subjective nihilism, for it alone
provides the necessary foundations to make the facts intelligible. This being
the case, the Christian is able to glean what is good from postmodernism, and
reject the extremes.
Individual
identity is fundamentally dependent on the mediation of the others. The self
appears to be dependent on the other in its being. It is through intercourse
with others that one finds one’s self. I am, says Hegel, a being in myself, but
only by myself through another. The individual perceives himself, in an
inseparable way, in relation to the others and in relations to himself, but
without the intervention of the others he would not be able to perceive
himself.
Apart
from being dependent on the intervention of the others in producing his own
understanding of himself, the individual is dependent on creating a positive
image of himself in order to endure himself and his surroundings. First and
foremost, the positive image of self-esteem should be brought about by and in
the individual himself, but it is dependent on the others’ gaze. Self-esteem is
created through action and negotiation with others, by committing oneself, by
playing a role for the others and for oneself. In other words, built in to the
identity as a process is a striving for self-esteem, and this self-esteem is
shaped by doing. Thus, identity is not only a matter of evoking an image of
oneself. One seeks other people’s respect and confidence. In order to become
something in one’s own eyes one must feel appreciated by others for what one is
and what one does. It is not only a matter of just being there, but of being of
importance, of making a difference.
As
a result of these ingredients - technology, human ingenuity and our own needs
and desires - we have created a society in which much of the culture and
politics, as well as the economy, is geared toward mass producing, and
consuming, simulations. It is a society in which many simulations are intended
to be mistaken for the real thing. But it is also a society in which
simulations that were never meant to be misleading often end up being mistaken
for what they resemble, by accident, thus making simulation confusion, like
pollution and traffic jams, another unintended, and toxic, byproduct of
technology.
Fortunately,
as simulations extend their reach, we are developing new survival skills that
help us to unmask illusions.
In
societies where modern conditions of production prevail, all of life presents
itself as an immense accumulation of spectacles. Everything that was
directly lived has moved away into a representation.
The images
detached from every aspect of life fuse in a common stream in which the unity
of this life can no longer be reestablished. Reality considered partially
unfolds, in its own general unity, as a pseudo-world apart, an object of mere
contemplation. The specialization of images of the world is completed in the
world of the autonomous image, where the liar has lied to himself. The
spectacle in general, as the concrete inversion of life, is the autonomous
movement of the non-living.
The
spectacle presents itself simultaneously as all of society, as part of society,
and as instrument of unification. As a part of society it is
specifically the sector which concentrates all gazing and all consciousness.
Due to the very fact that this sector is separate, it is the common
ground of the deceived gaze and of false consciousness, and the unification it
achieves is nothing but an official language of generalized separation.
The
spectacle is not a collection of images, but a social relation among people,
mediated by images.
The
spectacle cannot be understood as an abuse of the world of vision, as a product
of the techniques of mass dissemination of images. It is, rather, a Weltanschauung
which has become actual, materially translated. It is a world vision which has
become objectified.
The
spectacle grasped in its totality is both the result and the project of the
existing mode of production. It is not a supplement to the real world, an
additional decoration. It is the heart of the unrealism of the real society. In
all its specific forms, as information or propaganda, as advertisement or
direct entertainment consumption, the spectacle is the present model of
socially dominant life. It is the omnipresent affirmation of the choice already
made in production and its corollary consumption. The spectacle's form and
content are identically the total justification of the existing system's
conditions and goals. The spectacle is also the permanent presence of
this justification, since it occupies the main part of the time lived outside
of modern production.
Separation
is itself part of the unity of the world, of the global social praxis split up
into reality and image. The social practice which the autonomous spectacle
confronts is also the real totality which contains the spectacle. But the split
within this totality mutilates it to the point of making the spectacle appear
as its goal. The language of the spectacle consists of signs of the
ruling production, which at the same time are the ultimate goal of this
production.
One cannot
abstractly contrast the spectacle to actual social activity: such a division is
itself divided. The spectacle which inverts the real is in fact produced. Lived
reality is materially invaded by the contemplation of the spectacle while
simultaneously absorbing the spectacular order, giving it positive
cohesiveness. Objective reality is present on both sides. Every notion fixed
this way has no other basis than its passage into the opposite: reality rises
up within the spectacle, and the spectacle is real. This reciprocal alienation
is the essence and the support of the existing society.
The concept
of spectacle unifies and explains a great diversity of apparent phenomena. The
diversity and the contrasts are appearances of a socially organized appearance,
the general truth of which must itself be recognized. Considered in its own
terms, the spectacle is affirmation of appearance and affirmation of all
human life, namely social life, as mere appearance. But the critique which
reaches the truth of the spectacle exposes it as the visible negation of
life, as a negation of life which has become visible.
To describe
the spectacle, its formation, its functions and the forces which tend to
dissolve it, one must artificially distinguish certain inseparable elements.
When analyzing the spectacle one speaks, to some extent, the language of
the spectacular itself in the sense that one moves through the methodological
terrain of the very society which expresses itself in the spectacle. But the
spectacle is nothing other than the sense of the total practice of a
social-economic formation, its use of time. It is the historical
movement in which we are caught.
The
spectacle presents itself as something enormously positive, indisputable and
inaccessible. It says nothing more than "that which appears is good, that
which is good appears. The attitude which it demands in principle is passive
acceptance which in fact it already obtained by its manner of appearing without
reply, by its monopoly of appearance.
The
basically tautological character of the spectacle flows from the simple fact
that its means are simultaneously its ends. It is the sun which never sets over
the empire of modern passivity. It covers the entire surface of the world and
bathes endlessly in its own glory.
The society
which rests on modern industry is not accidentally or superficially
spectacular, it is fundamentally spectaclist. In the spectacle, which is
the image of the ruling economy, the goal is nothing, development everything.
The spectacle aims at nothing other than itself.
As the
indispensable decoration of the objects produced today, as the general
exposé of the rationality of the system, as the advanced economic sector
which directly shapes a growing multitude of image-objects, the spectacle is
the main production of present-day society.
The
spectacle subjugates living men to itself to the extent that the economy has
totally subjugated them. It is no more than the economy developing for itself.
It is the true reflection of the production of things, and the false
objectification of the producers.
The first
phase of the domination of the economy over social life brought into the
definition of all human realization the obvious degradation of being
into having. The present phase of total occupation of social life by the
accumulated results of the economy leads to a generalized sliding of having
into appearing, from which all actual "having" must draw its
immediate prestige and its ultimate function. At the same time all individual
reality has become social reality directly dependent on social power and shaped
by it. It is allowed to appear only to the extent that it is not.
Where the
real world changes into simple images, the simple images become real beings and
effective motivations of hypnotic behavior. The spectacle, as a tendency to
make one see the world by means of various specialized mediations (it can
no longer be grasped directly), naturally finds vision to be the privileged
human sense which the sense of touch was for other epochs; the most abstract,
the most mystifiable sense corresponds to the generalized abstraction of
present-day society. But the spectacle is not identifiable with mere gazing,
even combined with hearing. It is that which escapes the activity of men, that
which escapes reconsideration and correction by their work. It is the opposite
of dialogue. Wherever there is independent representation, the spectacle
reconstitutes itself.
The
spectacle inherits all the weaknesses of the Western philosophical
project which undertook to comprehend activity in terms of the categories of seeing;
furthermore, it is based on the incessant spread of the precise technical
rationality which grew out of this thought. The spectacle does not realize
philosophy, it philosophizes reality. The concrete life of everyone has been
degraded into a speculative universe.
Philosophy,
the power of separate thought and the thought of separate power, could never by
itself supersede theology. The spectacle is the material reconstruction of the
religious illusion. Spectacular technology has not dispelled the religious
clouds where men had placed their own powers detached from themselves; it has
only tied them to an earthly base. The most earthly life thus becomes opaque
and unbreathable. It no longer projects into the sky but shelters within itself
its absolute denial, its fallacious paradise. The spectacle is the technical
realization of the exile of human powers into a beyond; it is separation
perfected within the interior of man.
To the
extent that necessity is socially dreamed, the dream becomes necessary. The
spectacle is the nightmare of imprisoned modern society which ultimately
expresses nothing more than its desire to sleep. The spectacle is the guardian
of sleep.
The fact
that the practical power of modern society detached itself and built an
independent empire in the spectacle can be explained only by the fact that this
practical power continued to lack cohesion and remained in contradiction with
itself.
The oldest
social specialization, the specialization of power, is at the root of the
spectacle. The spectacle is thus a specialized activity which speaks for all
the others. It is the diplomatic representation of hierarchic society to
itself, where all other expression is banned. Here the most modern is also the
most archaic.
The
spectacle is the existing order's uninterrupted discourse about itself, its
laudatory monologue. It is the self-portrait of power in the epoch of its
totalitarian management of the conditions of existence. The fetishistic, purely
objective appearance of spectacular relations conceals the fact that they are
relations among men and classes: a second nature with its fatal laws seems to
dominate our environment. But the spectacle is not the necessary product of
technical development seen as a natural development. The society of the
spectacle is on the contrary the form which chooses its own technical content.
If the spectacle, taken in the limited sense of "mass media" which
are its most glaring superficial manifestation, seems to invade society as mere
equipment, this equipment is in no way neutral but is the very means suited to
its total self-movement. If the social needs of the epoch in which such
techniques are developed can only be satisfied through their mediation, if the
administration of this society and all contact among men can no longer take
place except through the intermediary of this power of instantaneous communication,
it is because this "communication" is essentially unilateral.
The concentration of "communication" is thus an accumulation, in the
hands of the existing system s administration, of the means which allow it to
carry on this particular administration. The generalized cleavage of the
spectacle is inseparable from the modern State, namely from the general
form of cleavage within society, the product of the division of social labor
and the organ of class domination.
Separation
is the alpha and omega of the spectacle. The institutionalization of the social
division of labor, the formation of classes, had given rise to a first sacred
contemplation, the mythical order with which every power shrouds itself from
the beginning. The sacred has justified the cosmic and ontological order which
corresponded to the interests of the masters; it has explained and embellished
that which society could not do. Thus all separate power has been
spectacular, but the adherence of all to an immobile image only signified the common
acceptance of an imaginary prolongation of the poverty of real social activity,
still largely felt as a unitary condition. The modern spectacle, on the
contrary, expresses what society can do, but in this expression the permitted
is absolutely opposed to the possible. The spectacle is the preservation
of unconsciousness within the practical change of the conditions of existence.
It is its own product, and it has made its own rules: it is a pseudo-sacred
entity. It shows what it is: separate power developing in itself, in the
growth of productivity by means of the incessant refinement of the division of
labor into a parcellization of gestures which are then dominated by the
independent movement of machines; and working for an ever-expanding market. All
community and all critical sense are dissolved during this movement in which
the forces that could grow by separating are not yet reunited.
With the
generalized separation of the worker and his products, every unitary view of
accomplished activity and all direct personal communication among producers are
lost. Accompanying the progress of accumulation of separate products and the
concentration of the productive process, unity and communication become the
exclusive attribute of the system's management. The success of the economic
system of separation is the proletarianization of the world.
Due to the
success of separate production as production of the separate, the fundamental
experience which in primitive societies is attached to a central task is in the
process of being displaced, at the crest of the system's development. by
non-work, by inactivity. But this inactivity is in no way liberated from
productive activity: it depends on productive activity and is an uneasy and
admiring submission to the necessities and results of production; it is itself
a product of its rationality. There can be no freedom outside of activity, and
in the context of the spectacle all activity is negated. just as real activity
has been captured in its entirety for the global construction of this result.
Thus the present "liberation from labor," the increase of leisure, is
in no way a liberation within labor, nor a liberation from the world shaped by
this labor. None of the activity lost in labor can be regained in the submission
to its result.
The economic
system founded on isolation is a circular production of isolation. The
technology is based on isolation, and the technical process isolates in turn.
From the automobile to television, all the goods selected by the
spectacular system are also its weapons for a constant reinforcement of the
conditions of isolation of "lonely crowds." The spectacle constantly
rediscovers its own assumptions more concretely.
The
spectacle originates in the loss of the unity of the world, and the gigantic
expansion of the modern spectacle expresses the totality of this loss: the
abstraction of all specific labor and the general abstraction of the entirety
of production are perfectly rendered in the spectacle, whose mode of being
concrete is precisely abstraction. In the spectacle, one part of the world represents
itself to the world and is superior to it. The spectacle is nothing more
than the common language of this separation. What binds the spectators together
is no more than an irreversible relation at the very center which maintains
their isolation. The spectacle reunites the separate, but reunites it as
separate.
The
alienation of the spectator to the profit of the contemplated object (which is
the result of his own unconscious activity) is expressed in the following way:
the more he contemplates the less he lives; the more he accepts recognizing
himself in the dominant images of need, the less he understands his own
existence and his own desires. The externality of the spectacle in relation to the
active man appears in the fact that his own gestures are no longer his but
those of another who represents them to him. This is why the spectator feels at
home nowhere, because the spectacle is everywhere.
The worker
does not produce himself; he produces an independent power. The success
of this production, its abundance, returns to the producer as an abundance
of dispossession. All the time and space of his world become foreign
to him with the accumulation of his alienated products. The spectacle is the
map of this new world, a map which exactly covers its territory. The very
powers which escaped us show themselves to us in all their force.
The
spectacle within society corresponds to a concrete manufacture of alienation.
Economic expansion is mainly the expansion of this specific industrial
production. What grows with the economy in motion for itself can only be the
very alienation which was at its origin.
Separated from his product, man
himself produces all the details of his world with ever increasing power, and
thus finds himself ever more separated from his world. The more his life is now
his product, the more lie is separated from his life.
The spectacle is capital
to such a degree of accumulation that it becomes an image.
|